Results for 'Disenchanting Senses : Law'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Andrea Pavoni.Disenchanting Senses : Law & the Taste of The Real - 2018 - In Andreas Philippopoulos-Mihalopoulos (ed.), Routledge Handbook of Law and Theory. New York, NY: Routledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Nicola Masciandario.Synaesthesia : The Mystical Sense Of Law - 2018 - In Andreas Philippopoulos-Mihalopoulos (ed.), Routledge Handbook of Law and Theory. New York, NY: Routledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  20
    The spaces of narrative consciousness: Or, what is your event?Law Alsobrook - 2015 - Technoetic Arts 13 (3):239-244.
    Cyberspace, a term popularized in the 1984 novel Neuromancer, was used by William Gibson to describe the ‘consensual hallucination’ and interstitial online world that lies between the reality of our world and that of the surreal terrain of dreamscapes. While many attempts have been made to describe this intangible, yet seemingly perceptible space, the digital domain as a metaphor mirrors in many ways our own inadequate understanding of consciousness. Conversely, the physicist Michio Kaku explains that our reality is bounded by (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  10
    30-Second Philosophies: The 50 Most Thought-Provoking Philosophies, Each Explained in Half a Minute.Barry Loewer, Stephen Law & Julian Baggini (eds.) - 2009 - New York: Metro Books.
    Language & Logic -- Glossary -- Aristotle's syllogisms -- Russell's paradox & Frege's logicism -- profile: Aristotle -- Russell's theory of description -- Frege's puzzle -- Gödel's theorem -- Epimenides' liar paradox -- Eubulides' heap -- Science & Epistemology -- Glossary -- I think therefore I am -- Gettier's counter example -- profile: Karl Popper -- The brain in a vat -- Hume's problem of induction -- Goodman's gruesome riddle -- Popper's conjectures & refutations -- Kuhn's scientific revolutions -- Mind (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  75
    The puzzle of hyper‐change.Andrew Law - 2018 - Ratio 32 (1):1-11.
    If there is a second dimension of time – a so-called ‘hypertime’ – is it logically possible for the past to change? Some have said yes; others have said no. I say yes provided that one has the appropriate ontological view of hypertime. So far, the ontology of hypertime has seldom been discussed. As such, this paper not only defends the logical possibility of a changing past, but aims to start a discussion on what ontological commitments are required to make (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  6.  39
    The Global Language of Human Rights: A Computational Linguistic Analysis.David S. Law - 2018 - The Law and Ethics of Human Rights 12 (1):111-150.
    Human rights discourse has been likened to a global lingua franca, and in more ways than one, the analogy seems apt. Human rights discourse is a language that is used by all yet belongs uniquely to no particular place. It crosses not only the borders between nation-states, but also the divide between national law and international law: it appears in national constitutions and international treaties alike. But is it possible to conceive of human rights as a global language or lingua (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  7.  54
    Humanism: a very short introduction.Stephen Law - 2011 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    Stephen Law explores how humanism uses science and reason to make sense of the world, looking at how it encourages individual moral responsibility and shows ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8. Evil pleasure is good for you!Iain Law - 2008 - Ethic@ - An International Journal for Moral Philosophy 7 (1):15-23.
    Many people are uncomfortable with the idea that pleasure from certain sources is genuinely beneficial. These sources can be sorted into two classes: ones that involve others’ pain; and ones that involve what seems to be damage rather than benefit to the person involved. Here’s an example of the latter: a woman who claims that she enjoys her work performing in hard-core pornographic films. Some find it hard to take such a claim at face value – they instinctively assume that (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  7
    Performance, subjectivity, and experimentation.Catherine Laws (ed.) - 2020 - Leuven: Leuven University Press.
    Music reflects subjectivity and identity: that idea is now deeply ingrained in both musicology and popular media commentary. The study of music across cultures and practices often addresses the enactment of subjectivity "in" music - how music expresses or represents "an' individual or "a" group. However, a sense of selfhood is also formed and continually reformed through musical practices, not least performance. How does this take place? How might the work of practitioners reveal aspects of this process? In what sense (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  10
    Voices, bodies, practices: performing musical subjectivities.Catherine Laws - 2019 - Leuven (Belgium): Leuven University Press. Edited by William Brooks, David Gorton, Thanh Thủy Nguyễn, Stefan Östersjö & Jeremy J. Wells.
    Who is the 'I' that performs? The arts of the twentieth and twenty-first centuries have pushed us relentlessly to reconsider our notions of the self, expression, and communication: to ask ourselves, again and again, who we think we are and how we can speak meaningfully to one another. Although in other performing arts studies, especially of theatre, the performance of selfhood and identity continues to be a matter of lively debate in both practice and theory, the question of how a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Objectivity in law.Veronica Rodriguez-Blanco - 2010 - Philosophy Compass 5 (3):240-249.
    In the first part of this paper, I discuss the different kinds of objectivity; general and legal objectivity more specifically. In the second part, I endeavour to explain the two main views that have been advanced to answer four core questions on legal objectivity. The first is whether moral and legal values are objective. Second, what is the nature of the relationship between legal and moral values? The third is whether, due to the specific nature of law, we should consider (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. Making sense of laws of physics.Alan Chalmers - 1999 - In Howard Sankey (ed.), Causation and Laws of Nature. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 3--16.
  13.  53
    The Sense of Appropriateness: Application Discourses in Morality and Law.Klaus Gunther - 1993 - State University of New York Press.
    In the third and fourth parts of the book, Günther shows--in debate with Hare, Dworkin, and others--how argumentation on the appropriate application of norms and principles in morality and law is possible.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  14. Review: Murray Shanahan, Solving the Frame Problem. A Mathematical Investigation of the Common Sense Law of Inertia. [REVIEW]Michael Gelfond - 1998 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 63 (3):1186-1188.
  15.  25
    Shanahan Murray. Solving the frame problem. A mathematical investigation of the common sense law of inertia. Artificial intelligence series. The MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass., and London, 1997, xxxiv + 407 pp. [REVIEW]Michael Gelfond - 1998 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 63 (3):1186-1188.
  16.  28
    Making Sense of Kant’s Formula of Universal Law: On Kleingeld’s Volitional Self-Contradiction Interpretation.Mark Timmons - 2023 - Philosophia 51 (2):463-475.
    This article examines Pauline Kleingeld’s “volitional self-contradiction” (VSC) interpretation of Kant’s formula of universal law. It begins in §1 with an outline of Kleingeld’s interpretation and then proceeds in §2 to raise some worries about how the interpretation handles Kant’s egoism example. §3 considers VSC’s handling of the false promise example comparing it in §4 with the Logical/Causal Law (LCL) interpretation, which arguably does better than its VSC competitor in handling this example. §5 deploys the LCL interpretation to consider the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  17. Making Sense of Sexual Harassment Law.Andrew Altman - 1996 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 25 (1):36-50.
  18. Sense and Basic Law V in Frege's logicism.Jan Harald Alnes - 1999 - Nordic Journal of Philosophical Logic 4:1-30.
  19.  3
    Common Sense Problems in Positive Law.Chris Berger - 2021 - The Lonergan Review 12:103-124.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  5
    Making sense of assessment in medical ethics and law.A. Dowie - 2014 - Journal of Medical Ethics 40 (10):717-718.
  21.  3
    The Sense of Appropriateness: Application Discourses in Morality and Law.John Farrell (ed.) - 1993 - State University of New York Press.
    Günther’s book demonstrates that most objections to moral and legal principles are directed not against the validity of principles but against the manner of their application. If one distinguishes between the justification of a principle and its appropriate application, then the claim that the application of the principle in each individual case follows automatically from its universal justification proves to be a misunderstanding. Günther develops this distinction with the help of Habermas’s discourse theory of morality. He then employs it to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  18
    Common Sense Rhetorical Theory, Pluralism, and Protestant Natural Law.Rosaleen Keefe - 2013 - Journal of Scottish Philosophy 11 (2):213-228.
    This paper offers re-assessment of Scottish Common Sense rhetoric and its relationship to pluralist practice and philosophical method. It argues that the rhetorical texts of George Campbell, Hugh Blair, and Alexander Bain can be read as a practical application of Scottish Common Sense philosophy. This offers a novel means of examining the relationship that Scottish rhetoric has to the philosophy of David Hume and also its own innovative philosophy of language. Finally, I argue that Scottish rhetoric makes a unique contribution (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Law and emotion: how empathy forms judges' sense of justice.Marcelo Campos Galuppo - 2019 - In M. N. S. Sellers, Joshua James Kassner & Colin Starger (eds.), The value and purpose of law: essays in honor of M.N.S. Sellers. Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag.
  24.  15
    Making Sense out of a Necessary Connection between Law and Morality.Timothy C. Shiell - 1987 - Public Affairs Quarterly 1 (3):77-90.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  15
    Common law and common sense.Michael Lobban - 2008 - Ratio Juris 21 (4):541-546.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. Making sense of libertarian free will : consciousness, science and laws of nature.Robert Kane - 2019 - In Allan McCay & Michael Sevel (eds.), Free Will and the Law: New Perspectives. New York, NY: Routledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  24
    Possession: Common Sense and Law.R. S. Bhalla - 1992 - Ratio Juris 5 (1):79-91.
    Abstract.This article is written with a view to clarifying the following points: First, to understand the nature of possession, its origin must be kept in mind. Possession is not a legal invention, it is a pre‐legal fact. Second, possession whether in law or in common sense is a de facto control. There is no difference between possession in law and possession in fact. Third, different types of rules and policies of law to deal with possession, do not change the contents (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  96
    Frege on Sense Identity, Basic Law V, and Analysis.Philip A. Ebert - 2016 - Philosophia Mathematica 24 (1):9-29.
    The paper challenges a widely held interpretation of Frege's conception of logic on which the constituent clauses of basic law V have the same sense. I argue against this interpretation by first carefully looking at the development of Frege's thoughts in Grundlagen with respect to the status of abstraction principles. In doing so, I put forth a new interpretation of Grundlagen §64 and Frege's idea of ‘recarving of content’. I then argue that there is strong evidence in Grundgesetze that Frege (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  29.  67
    Instinct of Nature: Natural Law, Synderesis, and the Moral Sense.Robert A. Greene - 1997 - Journal of the History of Ideas 58 (2):173-198.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Instinct of Nature: Natural Law, Synderesis, and the Moral SenseRobert A. Greene“Instinct is a great matter.”—Sir John FalstaffThis essay traces the evolution of the meaning of the expression instinctus naturae in the discussion of the natural law from Justinian’s Digest through its association with synderesis to Francis Hutcheson’s theory of the moral sense. The introduction of instinctus naturae into Ulpian’s definition of the natural law by Isidore of Seville (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  30. Adam Smith. Skeptical Newtonianism, Disenchanted Republicanism, and the Birth of Social Science.Sergio Volodia Marcello Cremaschi - 1987 - In Marcelo Dascal & Ora Gruengrad (eds.), Knowledge and Politics: Case Studies on the Relationship between Epistemology and Political Philosophy. Boulder, CO: Westview Press. pp. 83-110.
    Both Adam Smith's epistemology and his politics head to a stalemate. The former is under the opposing pulls of an essentialist ideal of knowledge and of a pragmatist approach to the history of science. The latter still tries to provide a foundation for a natural law, while conceiving it as non-absolute and changeable. The consequences are (i) inability to complete both the political and the epistemological works projected by Smith; (ii) decentralization of the social order, giving rise to several partial (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  31.  23
    Moral authority in law and criminal justice: Some reflections on Wilson's The Moral Sense.Tom R. Tyler & Wayne Kerstetter - 1994 - Criminal Justice Ethics 13 (2):44-53.
    (1994). Moral authority in law and criminal justice: Some reflections on Wilson's The Moral Sense. Criminal Justice Ethics: Vol. 13, No. 2, pp. 44-53.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  32
    Scottish common sense and nineteenth-century american law: A critical appraisal.John Mikhail - 2008
    In her insightful and stimulating article, The Mind of a Moral Agent, Professor Susanna Blumenthal traces the influence of Scottish Common Sense philosophy on early American law. Among other things, Blumenthal argues that the basic model of moral agency upon which early American jurists relied, which drew heavily from Common Sense philosophers like Thomas Reid, generated certain paradoxical conclusions about legal responsibility that later generations were forced to confront. "Having cast their lot with the Common Sense philosophers in the "formative (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  61
    Suing One's Sense Faculties for Fraud: 'Justifiable Reliance' in the Law as a Clue to Epistemic Justification.Christopher R. Green - 2007 - Philosophical Papers 36 (1):49-90.
    The law requires that plaintiffs in fraud cases be 'justified' in relying on a misrepresentation. I deploy the accumulated intuitions of the law to defend externalist accounts of epistemic justification and knowledge against Laurence BonJour's counterexamples involving clairvoyance. I suggest that the law can offer a well-developed model for adding a no-defeater condition to either justification or knowledge but without requiring that subjects possess positive reasons to believe in the reliability of an epistemic source.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Law as a Test of Conceptual Strength.Matthieu Queloz - forthcoming - In Veronica Rodriguez-Blanco, Daniel Peixoto Murata & Julieta A. Rabanos (eds.), Bernard Williams on Law and Jurisprudence: From Agency and Responsibility to Methodology. Oxford: Hart.
    In ‘What Has Philosophy to Learn from Tort Law?’, Bernard Williams reaffirms J. L. Austin’s suggestion that philosophy might learn from tort law ‘the difference between practical reality and philosophical frivolity’. Yet while Austin regarded tort law as just another repository of time-tested concepts, on a par with common sense as represented by a dictionary, Williams argues that ‘the use of certain ideas in the law does more to show that those ideas have strength than is done by the mere (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  11
    Uncommon sense: Jeremy Bentham, queer aesthetics, and the politics of taste.Carrie D. Shanafelt - 2021 - Charlottesville: University of Virginia Press.
    In his extensive private manuscripts, Jeremy Bentham used same-sex male intimacy as a philosophical test-case for the full political and social enfranchisement of women, colonized and enslaved persons, and sexual nonconformists. Bentham argued that oppression in law, philosophy, religion, and literature were all based on aesthetic hierarchies that refused to acknowledge differences of taste in sensory pleasure, including sexual pleasure. In Uncommon Sense, Carrie Shanafelt reads Bentham's sexual nonconformity papers as an argument for the toleration of aesthetic difference as the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  36
    Science, common sense and common law: Courtroom inquiries and the public understanding of science.Michael Lynch & Ruth Mcnally - 1999 - Social Epistemology 13 (2):183-196.
  37.  41
    The Sense of the Appropriate. Application Discourses in Morality and Law. [REVIEW]Urs Kindhäuser - 1991 - Philosophy and History 24 (1-2):17-18.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  42
    Overcoming law.Richard A. Posner (ed.) - 1995 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    Throughout, the book is unified by Posner's distinctive stance, which is pragmatist in philosophy, economic in methodology, and liberal (in the sense of John ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  39. Animals and the Law: Cruelty, Property, Rights... Or How the Law Makes up in Common Sense What It May Lack in Metaphysics.Jerrold Tannenbaum - 1995 - Social Research: An International Quarterly 62.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  40.  21
    Natural law and justice.Lloyd L. Weinreb - 1987 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    "Human beings are a part of nature and apart from it." The argument of Natural Law and Justice is that the philosophy of natural law and contemporary theories about the nature of justice are both efforts to make sense of the fundamental paradox of human experience: individual freedom and responsibility in a causally determined universe. Professor Weinreb restores the original understanding of natural law as a philosophy about the place of humankind in nature. He traces the natural law tradition from (...)
  41. Natural law and the theory of property: Grotius to Hume.Stephen Buckle - 1991 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    In this book, Buckle provides a historical perspective on the political philosophies of Locke and Hume, arguing that there are continuities in the development of seventeenth and eighteenth-century political theory which have often gone unrecognized. He begins with a detailed exposition of Grotius's and Pufendorf's modern natural law theory, focussing on their accounts of the nature of natural law, human sociability, the development of forms of property, and the question of slavery. He then shows that Locke's political theory takes up (...)
  42.  8
    Sense of Community and its Sustenance in Africa.Olatunji Oyeshile - 2007 - Human Affairs 17 (2):230-240.
    Sense of Community and its Sustenance in Africa There is no gainsaying the fact that Africa is inundated with many problems which have made the development and the attainment of social order, conceived in normative terms, daunting tasks. It is also a fact that there are many causes of this scenario such as political marginalization, ethnic chauvinism, economic mismanagement, religious bigotry and corruption in its various facets. However, in this disquisition we identify the lack of the development, internalization and application (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. The White Mob, (In) Equality Before the Law, and Racial Common Sense: A Critical Race Reading of the Negro Question in “Reflections on Little Rock”.Ainsley LeSure - 2021 - Political Theory 49 (1):3-27.
    This article argues that Hannah Arendt’s controversial essay “Reflections on Little Rock,” when situated within her analysis of Jewish assimilation, has an astute insight: racial integration and the decrease of the racial gaps in material inequality, without taking seriously the political project of building a world in common, only intensify racism in racist polities. This occurs because attempts to extend formal equality to the racially dominated give rise to the rule of racial common sense, a result of a clash between (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  44. Facts, Artifacts, and Law-Given Reasons.Noam Gur - 2022 - In Luka Burazin, Kenneth Einar Himma, Corrado Roversi & Paweł Banaś (eds.), The Artifactual Nature of Law. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar Publishing. pp. 199–222.
    This chapter centers around law's capacity to constitute practical reasons. In discussing this theme, consideration is given to law's artifactual character. The discussion falls into two main parts. In Section 1, I critically examine a skeptical line of thought about law's capacity to constitute reasons for action, which draws, in part, on law's artifactuality. I argue for a somewhat less skeptical (but still qualified) stance, according to which the fact that a legal directive has been issued can (notwithstanding the artifactuality (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  64
    Constitutional law and religion.Perry Dane - 1996 - In Dennis Patterson (ed.), A Companion to Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 119–131.
    This essay on law and religion appears in the second edition of the Blackwell Companion to Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory, edited by Dennis Patterson. It is a revision of a similar entry in the book’s first edition. The essay opens by broadly discussing the complex relationships between law and religion writ large as movements in human history – social, cultural, intellectual, and institutional phenomena with distinct but often overlapping logics and concerns. It then hones in on the efforts (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46. Lawful Persistence.David Builes & Trevor Teitel - 2022 - Philosophical Perspectives 36 (1):5-30.
    The central aim of this paper is to use a particular view about how the laws of nature govern the evolution of our universe in order to develop and evaluate the two main competing options in the metaphysics of persistence, namely endurantism and perdurantism. We begin by motivating the view that our laws of nature dictate not only qualitative facts about the future, but also which objects will instantiate which qualitative properties. We then show that both traditional doctrines in the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  47. The Law of Non-Contradiction as a Metaphysical Principle.Tuomas E. Tahko - 2009 - Australasian Journal of Logic 7:32-47.
    The goals of this paper are two-fold: I wish to clarify the Aristotelian conception of the law of non-contradiction as a metaphysical rather than a semantic or logical principle, and to defend the truth of the principle in this sense. First I will explain what it in fact means that the law of non-contradiction is a metaphysical principle. The core idea is that the law of non-contradiction is a general principle derived from how things are in the world. For example, (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  48.  65
    A scientific account of meaning: Deflationary but not disenchanting.Donald Wiebe - 2009 - Zygon 44 (1):31-40.
    In The Really Hard Problem , Owen Flanagan maintains that accounting for meaning requires going beyond the resources of the physical, biological, social, and mind sciences. He notes that the religious myths and fantastical stories that once "funded" flourishing lives and made life meaningful have been epistemically discredited by science but nevertheless insists that meaning does exist and can be fully accounted for only in a form of systematic philosophical theorizing that is continuous with science and does not need to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  49. Sense and Objectivity in Frege's Logic.Gilead Bar-Elli - 2001 - In Albert Newen (ed.), Building on Frege. Stanford: pp. 91-111.
    Important aspects of its philosophical basis, and its significance for the foundations of mathematics, appeared in The Foundations of Mathematics (FA, 1884). Six years later, at the beginning of the 1890s, Frege published three articles that mark significant changes in his conception: "Function and Concept" (FC, 1891), "On Sense and Reference" (SR, 1892) and "Concept and Object" (1892). Notable among these changes are: (a) The systematic distinction between the sense and the reference of expressions as two separate ingredients of their (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  50.  19
    On Law and Reason.Aleksander Peczenik - 1989 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer Verlag.
    a This is an outline of a coherence theory of law. Its basic ideas are: reasonable support and weighing of reasons. All the rest is commentary.a (TM) These words at the beginning of the preface of this book perfectly indicate what On Law and Reason is about. It is a theory about the nature of the law which emphasises the role of reason in the law and which refuses to limit the role of reason to the application of deductive logic. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000